Article published in:
Finiteness and NominalizationEdited by Claudine Chamoreau and Zarina Estrada-Fernández
[Typological Studies in Language 113] 2016
► pp. 205–242
The role of nominalization in theticity
A Sikuani contribution
When speakers need to communicate a piece of information in which they allocate all the components the same degree of informational density – especially the components expressing the state of the world described and the entities associated with it – they rely on linguistic mechanisms that may differ radically from those employed in speech-acts that involve a rhematic element (rather dense informationally) linked to a thematic element (rather thin informationally). In languages where existential predication does not require a verb of existence with the subject as the thematic element, this type of construction is well adapted to the thetic communicative intention, since it is organized around a noun phrase conveying rhematic information that is not connected to any thematic element apart from the world, or the situation. Since this element is not instantiated linguistically, or at least not by expressions capable of referring, the structure of this kind of existential predication is monadic. This is the most striking difference between the formal correlates of thetic constructions and those of the dyadic construction with rheme and theme. The Sikuani language makes a great deal of use of verb nominalization machinery (which provides a way to combine in the most parsimonious way the state of affairs described and the entities associated with it) in order to fulfill the goal of thetic communication. In particular, by playing with these mechanisms this language manages to modulate the degree of semantic reification of the state of the world described by the nominalized verb. Consequently a nominalized form with a thetic function becomes able to express semantic configurations (events, states, etc.) similar to those normally expressed by finite verbs.
Keywords: existential predication, finiteness, nominal predication, nominalization, theticity
Published online: 23 June 2016
https://doi.org/10.1075/tsl.113.09que
https://doi.org/10.1075/tsl.113.09que
References
References
Carlin, Eithne
Casielles, Eugenia & Progovac, Ljiljana
Chacon, Thiago
2012 The Phonology and Morphology of Kubeo: The Documentation, Theory and Description of an Amazonian Language. PhD dissertation, University of Hawaii.
Fox, Barbara
Jelinek, Eloise
Kaufman, Daniel
Kuroda, S.-Y.
Lambrecht, Knud
1987 Aboutness as a cognitive category: The thetic-categorical distinction revisited. In
Proceedings of the Thirteenth Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society
, 366-381.
1988 There was a farmer had a dog: Syntactic amalgams revisited. In
Proceedings of the Fourteenth Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society
, 319-339.
Launey, Michel
Lewis, Sean Michael
2001 Rethinking the existence of the thetic judgment. http://www.swarthmore.edu/SocSci/Linguistics/Papers/2001/lewis_sean-michael.pdf
Mithun, Marianne
Potsdam, Eric
Progovac, Ljiljana
Queixalós, F.
Queixalós, Francesc & Jimenez Rosalba
Rosengren Inger
Schwartz, Anne
2010 Discourse principles in grammar: The thetic/categorical dichotomy. In
Proceedings of the Tropics of the Imagination Conference
, 2 November 2009, Cairns, James Cook University. http://www.jcu.edu.au/etropic/ET9/Schwarz.pdf
Shibatani, Masayoshi
Cited by
Cited by 1 other publications
Magalhães, Marina, Walkíria Praça & Aline Da Cruz
This list is based on CrossRef data as of 04 april 2021. Please note that it may not be complete. Sources presented here have been supplied by the respective publishers. Any errors therein should be reported to them.