Article published in:
The Constitution of Phenomenal Consciousness: Toward a science and theory
Edited by Steven M. Miller
[Advances in Consciousness Research 92] 2015
► pp. 418432
References
Adams, R.M.
(2013) Consciousness, physicalism, and panpsychism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 728–735. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Alter, T.
(1995) Mary’s new perspective. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 73(4), 582–584. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Baker, L.R.
(2007) The metaphysics of everyday life: An essay in practical realism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
(2013) Pereboom’s robust nonreductive physicalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 736–744. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R.
(1999) Kinds, complexity, and multiple realization: Comments on Millikan’s “Historical kinds and the special sciences”. Philosophical Studies, 95(1–2), 67–98. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T.
(1979) Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4(1), 73–121. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D.J.
(1996) The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2002) Does conceivability entail possibility? In T.S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp.145–200). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(2003) The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp.220–272). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D.J., & Jackson, F.
(2001) Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review, 110(3), 315–360. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P.M.
(1985) Reduction, qualia and the direct introspection of brain states. Journal of Philosophy, 82(1), 8–28. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D.
(1992) Quining qualia. In A.J. Marcel & E. Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in contemporary science (pp.42–77). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Goff, P.
forthcoming). Real acquaintance and physicalism. In P. Coates & S. Coleman (Eds.) Phenomenal qualities: Sense, perception, and consciousness Oxford, UK Oxford University Press
Jackson, F.
(1982) Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32(127), 127–136. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
(1986) What Mary didn’t know. Journal of Philosophy, 83(5), 291–295. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I.
(1781/1787/1998) Critique of pure reason (P. Guyer & A.W. Wood, Eds. and Trans.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G.W.
(1969) Philosophical papers and letters (2nd ed.), (L.E. Loemker, Ed. & Trans.). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: D. Reidel Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Locke, J.
(1689/1975) An essay concerning human understanding. In P.H. Nidditch (Ed.), The Clarendon edition of the works of John Locke. An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T.
(1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Ney, A.
(2007) Physicalism and our knowledge of intrinsic properties. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85(1), 41–60. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Nida-Rümelin, M.
(2010) Qualia: The knowledge argument. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2010 edition). Retrieved from http://​plato​.stanford​.edu​/archives​/sum2010​/entries​/qualia​-knowledge
Pereboom, D.
(1994) Bats, brain scientists, and the limitations of introspection. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54(2), 315–329. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
(2002) Robust nonreductive materialism. Journal of Philosophy, 99(10), 499–531. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
(2011) Consciousness and the prospects of physicalism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
(2013a) Précis of Consciousness and the Prospects of Physicalism . Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 715–727. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
(2013b) Replies to Daniel Stoljar, Robert Adams, and Lynne Baker. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 753–764. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Place, U.T.
(1956) Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47(1), 44–50. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, A.
(1996) Epistemic probability and evil. In D. Howard-Snyder (Ed.), The evidential argument from evil (pp.69–96). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B.
(1927) The analysis of matter. London, UK: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.Google Scholar
Smart, J.J.C.
(1959) Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68(2), 141–156. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, D.
(2013) Qualitative inaccuracy and unconceived alternatives. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 745–752. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
van Cleve, J.
(1988) Inner states and outer relations: Kant and the case for monadism. In P.H. Hare (Ed.), Doing philosophy historically (pp.231–247). Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar